Monday, August 31, 2015

The slower, harder ways to increase reproducibility

tl;dr: The second of a two part series. Recommendations for improving reproducibility – many require slowing down or making hard decisions, rather than simply following a different rule than you followed before.

In my previous post, I wrote about my views on some proposed changes in scientific practice to increase reproducibility. Much has been made of preregistration, publication of null results, and Bayesian statistics as important changes to how we do business. But my view is that there is relatively little value in appending these modifications to a scientific practice that is still about one-off findings; and applying them mechanistically to a more careful, cumulative practice is likely to be more of a hindrance than a help. So what do we do? Here are the modifications to practice that I advocate (and try to follow myself).

1. Cumulative study sets with internal replication. 

If I had to advocate for a single change to practice, this would be it. In my lab we never do just one study on a topic, unless there are major constraints of cost or scale that prohibit that second study. Because one study is never decisive.* Build your argument cumulatively, using the same paradigm, and include replications of the key effect along with negative controls. This cumulative construction provides "pre-registration" of analyses – you need to keep your analytic approach and exclusion criteria constant across studies. It also gives you a good intuitive estimate of the variability of your effect across samples. The only problem is that it's harder and slower than running one-off studies. Tough. The resulting quality is orders of magnitude higher. 

If you show me a one-off study and I fail to replicate it in my lab, I will tend to suspect that you got lucky or p-hacked your way to a result. But if you show me a package of studies with four internal replications of an effect, I will believe that you know how to get that effect – and if I don't get it, I'll think that I'm doing something wrong. 

2. Everything open by default.

There is a huge psychological effect to doing all your work knowing that everyone will see all your data, your experimental stimuli, and your analyses. When you're tempted to write sloppy, uncommented code, you think twice. Unprincipled exclusions look even more unprincipled when you have to justify each line of your analysis.** And there are incredible benefits of releasing raw stimuli and data – reanalysis, reuse, and error checking. It can make you feel very exposed to have all your experimental data subject to reanalysis by reviewers or random trolls on the internet. But if there is an obvious, justifiable reanalysis that A) you didn't catch and B) provides evidence against your interpretation, you should be very grateful if someone finds it (and even more so if it's before publication).  

3. Larger N. 

Increasing sample sizes is a basic starting point that almost every study could benefit from. Simmons et al. (2011) advocated N=20 per cell then realized that was far too few; Vazire asks for 200, perhaps with her tongue in her cheek. I'm pretty darn sure there's no magic number. Psychophysics studies might need a dozen (or 59). Individual differences studies might need 10,000 or more. But if there's one thing we've learned from the recent focus on statistical power, estimating any effect accurately requires much more power than we expect. My rough guide is that the community standards for N in each subfield are almost always off by at least a factor of 2, just in terms of power for statistical significance. And they are off by a factor of 10 for collecting effect size estimates that will support model-based inferences.

4. Better visualizations of variability. 

If you run a lot of studies, show all of their results together in one big plot. And show us the variability of those measurements in a way that allows us to understand how much precision you have. Then we will know whether you really have evidence that you understand and whether you can consistently predict either the existence or the magnitude of an effect. Use 95% CIs or Bayesian credible intervals or HPD intervals or whatever strikes your fancy. Frequentist CIs do perform badly when you have just a handful of datapoints, but they do fine when N is large (see above). But come on: this one is obvious: Standard error of the mean is a terrible guide to inference. I care much less about frequentist or Bayesian and much, much more about whether it's 95% vs. 68%. 

5. Manipulation checks, positive controls, and negative controls. 

The reproducibility project was a huge success, and I'm very proud to have been part of it. But I felt that one intuition about replicability was missing from the assessment of the results: whether the experimenters thought they could have "fixed" the experiment. Meaning, there are some findings that when they fail to replication, you have no recourse – you have no idea what to do next. The original paper found a significant effect and a decent effect size, you find nothing. But there are other experiments where you know what happened, based on the pattern of results: the manipulation failed, or the population was different, or the baseline didn't work. In these studies, you typically know what to do next – strengthen the manipulation, alter the stimuli for the population, modify the baseline.

The paradigms you can "debug" – repeat iteratively to adjust them for your situation or population – typically have a number of internal controls. These usually include manipulation checks, positive controls, or negative controls (sometimes even all three). Manipulation checks tell you that the manipulation had the desired effect – e.g., if you are inducing people to identify with a particular group, they actually do, or if you are putting people under cognitive load they are actually under load. Negative controls show that in the absence of the manipulation there is no difference in the measure – they are a sanity check that other aspects of the experimental situation are not causing your effect. Positive controls tell you that some manipulation can cause a difference in your measure, hence it is a sensitive measure, even if the manipulation of interest fails. The output of these checks can provide a wealth of information about a failure to replicate and can lead to later successes.

6. Predictions from (quantitative) theory.

If all of our theories are vague, verbal one-offs then they provide very little constraint on our empirical measures. That's a terrible situation to be in as a scientist. If we can create quantitative theories that make empirical predictions, then these theories provide strong constraints on our data – if we don't observe a predicted pattern, we need to rethink either the model or the experiment. While neither one is guaranteed to be right, the theory provides an extra check on the data. I wrote more about this idea here.

7. A broader portfolio of publication outlets.

If every manipulation psychologists conducted were important, then we'd want to preregister and publish all of our findings. This situation is – arguably – the case in biomedicine. Every trial is a critical part of the overall outlook on a given drug, and most trials are expensive and risky, so they require regulation and care. But, like it or not, experimental psychology is different. Our work is cheap and typically poses little risk to participants, and there are an infinity of possible psychological manipulations that don't do anything and may never be of any importance.

So, as I've been arguing in previous posts, I think it's silly to advocate that psychologists publish all of their (null) results. There are plenty of reasons not to publish a null result: boringness, bad design, evidence of experimenter error, etc. Of course, there are some null results that are theoretically important and in those cases, we absolutely should publish. But my own research would grind to a halt if I had to write up all the dumb and unimportant things that I've pursued and dropped in the past few years.***

What we need is a broader set of publication outlets that allow us to publish all of the following: exciting new breakthroughs; theoretically deep, complex study sets; general incremental findings; run-of-the-mill replications; and messy, boring, or null results. No one journal can be the right home for all of these. In my view, there's a place for Science and Nature – or some idealized, academically-edited, open-access version of them. I love reading and writing short, broad, exciting reports of the best work on a topic. But there's also a place for journals where the standard is correctness and the reports can include whatever level of detail is necessary to document messy, boring, or null findings that nevertheless will be useful to others going forward. Think PLoS ONE, perhaps without the high article publication charge. The broader point is that we need a robust ecosystem of publication outlets – from high-profile to run-of-the-mill – and some of these outlets need to allow for publication of null results. But whether we publish in them should be a matter of our own scientific responsibility. 

Conclusions.

A theme running throughout all these recommendations is that I generally believe in all of the principles advocated by folks who want prereg, publication of nulls, and Bayesian data analysis. But their suggestions are almost always posed as mechanical rules: rules that you can follow and know that you are doing science the right way. But these rules should be tempered by our judgment. Preregister if you think that previous work doesn't sufficiently constrain analysis. Publish nulls if they are theoretically important. Use Bayesian tools if they afford some analytic advantages relative to their complexity. But don't do these things just because someone said to. Do them because – in your best scientific judgment – they improve the reliability and validity of the argument you are making.

-----
Thanks to Chris Potts for valuable discussion. Typos corrected afternoon 8/31.

* And, I don't know about you, but when I can only do one study, I always get it wrong. 
** I especially like this one: data <- data[data$subid != "S011",]. Damn you, subject 11.
*** I also can't think of anything more boring than reading Studies 1 – 14 in my paper titled "A crazy idea about word learning that never really should have worked anyway and, in the end, despite a false positive in Study 3, didn't amount to anything."

Thursday, August 27, 2015

A moderate's view of the reproducibility crisis

(Part 1 of a series of two blogposts on this topic. The second part is here.)

Reproducibility is a major problem in psychology and elsewhere. Much of the published literature is not solid enough to build on: experiences from my class suggest that students can get interesting stuff to work about half the time, at best. The recent findings of the reproducibility project only add to this impression.* And awareness has been growing about all kinds of potential problems for reproducibility, including p-hacking, file-drawer effects, and deeper issues in the frequentist data analysis tools many of us were originally trained on. What we should do about this problem?

Many people advocate dramatic changes to our day-to-day scientific practices. While I believe deeply in some of these changes – open practices being one example – I also worry that some recommendations will hinder the process of normal science. I'm what you might call a "reproducibility moderate." A moderate acknowledges the problem, but believes that the solutions should not be too radical. Instead, solutions should be chosen to conserve the best parts of our current practice.

Here are my thoughts on three popular proposed solutions to the reproducibility crisis: preregistration, publication of null results, and Bayesian statistics. In each case, I believe these techniques should be part of our scientific arsenal – but adopting them wholesale would cause more problems than it would fix.

Pre-registration. Pre-registering a study is an important technique for removing analytic degrees of freedom. But it also ties the analysts's hands in ways that can be cumbersome and unnecessary early in a research program, where analytic freedom is critical for making sense of the data (the trick is just not to publish those exploratory analyses as though they are confirmatory). As I've argued, preregistration is a great tool to have in your arsenal for large-scale or one-off studies. In cases where subsequent replications are difficult or overly costly, prereg allows you to have confidence in your analyses. But in cases where you can run a sequence of studies that build on one another, each replicating the key finding and using the same analysis strategy, you don't need to pre-register because your previous work naturally constrains your analysis. So: rather than running more one-off studies but preregistering them, we should be doing more cumulative, sequential work where – for the most part – preregistration isn't needed.

Publication of null findings. File drawer biases – where negative results are not published and so effect sizes are inflated across a literature – are a real problem, especially in controversial areas. But the solution is not to publish everything, willy-nilly! Publishing a paper, even a short one or a preprint, is a lot of work. The time you spend writing up null results is time you are not doing new studies. What we need is thoughtful consideration of when it is ethical to suppress a result, and when there is a clear need to publish.

Bayesian statistics. Frequentist statistical methods have deep conceptual flaws and are broken in any number of ways. But they can still be a useful tool for quantifying our uncertainty about data, and a wholesale abandonment of them in favor of Bayesian stats (or even worse, nothing!) risks several negative consequences. First, having a uniform statistical analysis paradigm facilitates evaluation of results. You don't have to be an expert to understand someone's ANOVA analysis. But if everyone uses one-off graphical models (as great as they are), then there are many mistakes we will never catch due to the complexity of the models. Second, the tools for Bayesian data analysis are getting better quickly, but they are nowhere near as easy to use as the frequentist ones. To pick on one system, as an experienced modeler, I love working with Stan. But until it stops crashing my R session, I will not recommend it as a tool for first-year graduate stats. In the mean time, I favor the Cumming solution: A more gentle move towards confidence intervals, judicious use of effect size, and a decrease in reliance on inferences from individual instances of p < .05.

Sometimes it looks like we've polarized into two groups: replicators and everyone else. This is crazy! Who wants to spend an entire career replicating other people's work, or even your own? Instead, replication needs to be part of our scientific process more generally. It needs to be a first step, where we build on pre-existing work, and a last step, where we confirm our findings prior to publication. But the steps in the middle – where you do the real discovery – are important as well. If we focus only on those first and last steps and make our recommendations in light of them alone, we forget the basic practice of science.

----
* I'm one of many, many authors of that project, having helped to contribute four replication projects from my graduate class.

Tuesday, July 14, 2015

Engineering the National Children's Study

The National Children's Study was a 100,000-child longitudinal study that would have tracked a cohort of children from birth to age 21, measuring environmental, family, genetic, and cognitive aspects of development at an unprecedented scale. Unfortunately, last year the NIH Director decided to shut the study down, following a highly critical report from the National Academy of Sciences that criticized a number of aspects of the study including its leadership and its sampling plan.

I got involved in the NCS about a year ago, when I was asked to be a part of the Cognitive Health team. Participating in the team has been an extremely positive experience, as I've had a chance to work with a great group of developmental researchers. We've met weekly for the past year, first to create plans for the cognitive portions of NCS, and later – after the study was cancelled – to discuss possible byproducts of the group's work. (Full disclosure: I am still a contractor for NCS and will be until the final windup is completed).

According to recent reports, though, NCS may be restarted by an act of Congress. As originally conceived, the study served a very valuable purpose: creating a sample large enough and diverse enough to allow analyses of rare outcomes, even for parts of the population that are often underrepresented in other cohorts. Other countries clearly think this is a good ideaAccording to one proposal, though, recruitment in the new study might piggyback on other ongoing studies. I'm not sure how this could work, given that different studies would likely have radically different measures, ages, and recruitment strategies. Even if some of these choices were coordinated, differences in implementation of the studies would make inferences from the data much more problematic.

I would love to see the original NCS vision carried to fruition. But even based on my limited perspective, I also understand why the project was extremely slow to start and ran into substantial cost obstacles. Creating such a massive design inevitably runs into problems of interlocking constraints, where decisions about recruitment depend on decisions about design and vice versa. Converging on the right measures is such a difficult process that by the time decisions are made, they are already out of date (a critique leveled also by the NAS report).

If the NCS is restarted, it will need a faster and cheaper planning process to have a chance of going forward to data collection. Here's my proposal: the NCS needs to work as if it's building a piece of software, not planning a conference. If you're planning a conference, you need to have stakeholders gradually reach consensus on details like the location, the program, and the events, before a single event occurs on a fixed timeline. But if you're building a software application, you need to respond to the constraints of your platform, adapt to your shifting user base, pilot test quickly and iteratively, and make sure that everything works before you release to market. This kind of agile optimization was missing from the previous iteration of the study. Here are three specific suggestions.

1. Iterative piloting. 

Nothing reveals the weaknesses of a study design like putting it into practice.  In a longitudinal study, the adoption of a bad measure, bad data storage platform, or bad sampling decision early on in the study will dramatically reduce the value of the subsequent data. It's a terrible feeling to collect data on a measure, knowing that the earlier baselines were flawed and the longitudinal analysis will be compromised.

The original NCS included a vanguard cohort of about 5,000 participants, mostly to test the recruitment strategy. (In fact, the costs of the vanguard study may have contributed to the cancelation of the main strategy). But one pilot program is not enough. All aspects of the program need to be piloted, so that the design can be adapted to the realities of the situation. From the length of the individual sessions, to the reliability of the measures and the retention rate across different populations, critical parts of the study all need to be tested multiple times before they are adopted.

The revised NCS should create a staged series of pilot samples of gradually increasing size, whose timeline is designed to allow iteration and incorporation of insights from previous samples. For example, if NCS v2 launches in 2022, then create cohorts of 100, 200, 1000, and 2000 to launch in 2018 – 21, respectively. Make the first samples longitudinal to test dropout (so the sampling design can be adjusted in the main study), and make the last sample cross-sectional so as to pilot test the precise measures that are planned for every age visit. Make it a rule: If any measure or decision is adopted in the final sample, there must be data on its reliability in the current study context.

2. Early adoption of precise infrastructure standards.  

Here's a basic example of an interlocking constraint satisfaction problem. You need to present measures to parents and collect and store the data resulting from these measures in a coherent data-management framework. But the way you collect the data and the way you store them interact with what the measures are. You can't know exactly how data from a measure (even one as simple as a survey) will look until you know how it will be collected. But you want to design the infrastructure for data collection around the measures that you need.

One way to solve this kind of problem is to iterate gradually into a solution. One committee discusses measures, a second discusses infrastructure. They discuss their needs, then meet, then discuss their needs again. Finally they converge and adopt a shared standard. This model can work well if the target you are optimizing to is static, e.g. if the answer stays the same during your deliberations. The problem is that technical infrastructure doesn't stay the same while you work – the best infrastructure is constantly changing. Good ideas for data management when the NCS began are no longer relevant. But if the infrastructure group is constantly changing the platform, then the folks creating the measures can't ever rely on particular functionality.

Software engineers solve this problem by creating design specifications that are implementation independent. In other words, everyone knows exactly what they need to deliver and what they can rely on others to deliver (and the under-the-hood details don't matter). Consider an API (application programming interface) for an eye-tracker. The experimenter doesn't know how the eye-tracker measures point of gaze, but she knows that if she calls a particular method, say getPointOfGaze, she will get back X and Y coordinates, accurate to some known tolerance. On the other end of the abstraction, the eye-tracker manufacturers don't need to know the details of the experiment in order to build the eye-tracker. They just need to getPointOfGaze quickly and accurately.

In a revised NCS, study architects should publish a technical design specification for all (behavioral) measures that is independent of method of administration. Such standards obviate hiring many layers of contractors to implement each set of measures separately. Instead, a single format conversion step can be engineered. For example, a standard survey XML format would be translated into the appropriate presentation format (whether the survey is presented on the phone, on the computer, or on a tablet or phone). As in many modern content management systems, the users of a measure could rapidly view and iterate on the precise implementation of the measure, rather than having to work through intermediaries.

A further engineering trick that could be applied to this setup is the use of automated testing and test suites. Given a known survey format and a uniform standard, it would be far easier to create automated tools to estimate completion time, to test data storage and integrity, and to search for bugs. Imagine if the NCS looked like an open-source software project, in which each "build" of the study protocol would be forced to pass a set of automated tests prior to piloting...

3. Independence of measure development and measure adoption.

Other people's children are great, but we all love our own the best. That's why we don't review our own papers or hire our own PhD students to be our colleagues. The adoption of measures into a longitudinal study is no different. If we allow the NCS to engage in measure development – creating new ways of measuring a particular environmental, physiological, or psychological construct – rather than simply adopting pre-existing standards, we need to take care that these measures are only adopted if they are the best option for fulfilling the study's goals.

Fix this problem by barring NCS designers from being involved in the creation of measures that are then used in the NCS. If the design committee wants a new measure, they must solicit competitive outside bids to create it and then adopt the version that has the most data supporting it in a direct evaluation. To do otherwise risks the inclusion of measures with insufficient evidence of reliability and validity.

This recommendation is based directly on my own experiences in the Cognitive Health team. Over the course of the last year, I've been very pleased to be able to help this team in the development of a new set of measures for profiling infant cognition. Based on automated eye-tracking methods, these measures have the potential to be a ground-breaking advance in understanding individual differences in cognition during infancy. I'm now quite invested in their success and I hope to continue working on them regardless of the outcome of the NCS study.

That's precisely the problem. I am no longer an objective observer of these measures! Had NCS gone forward I would have pushed for their adoption into the main study, even if the data on their efficacy were much more limited than should be necessary for adoption at a national scale. I'm not suggesting that NCS would adopt a really terrible measure. But given what we know about motivated cognition and the sunk cost fallacy, it's very likely that the bar would be lower for adopting an internally-developed measure than an external one.

If the NCS acts as a developer of new measures, there is a temptation to continue working to get the perfect suite of measurements, rather than to stop development and run the study. This is the great being the enemy of the good. If the NCS is a consumer of others' measures – on some rare occasions, measures that it has commissioned and evaluated – then it can more dispassionately adopt the best available option that fits the constraints of the study.

Conclusions

My own experiences with the NCS – limited as they are – have been nothing but positive. I've gotten to work with some great people, seen the initial development of an exciting new tool, and glimpsed the workings of a much larger project. But as I read about the fate of the study as a whole, I worry that the independence that's made my little part of the project so fun to work on – developing standards, envisioning new measures – is precisely why the project as a whole did not move forward.

What I've suggested here is that a new version of the NCS could benefit from an engineering mindset. Having internal deadlines for pilot launches would constrain planning with interim goals. Adding precise technical specifications and the abstractions necessary to work with them would add certainty to the planning process and eliminate many redundant contractors; for example, our new measures would probably be off the table simply because they wouldn't fit into the existing infrastructure. And an adversarial review of measures would better allow designers to weigh independent evidence for adoption.

In sum: bring back the NCS! But run it like you're building an app: one that has to fulfill a set of functions, yes, but also one that has to scale quickly and cheaply to unprecedented size.

---
Thanks to Steve Reznick, my colleague on the Cognitive Health team, for valuable comments on a previous draft. Views and errors are my own.  

Friday, July 10, 2015

New postdoc opportunity

(Update as of September, 2015: Position is now filled.)

My lab, the Language and Cognition Lab in the Psych Department at Stanford, is recruiting a postdoctoral fellow for a new project.

Parents are increasingly bombarded with information about how they should parent, often in terse formats like public service messages, brief videos, or even texts. But what do they take away from these messages? To answer this question, we're starting a new project on the pragmatics of communicating about parenting. Drawing on research in pedagogy, cognitive development, pragmatics, and social cognition, we will investigate what parents with different backgrounds learn from parenting messages, and how these messages affect their interactions with their children. Within this general framework there will be substantial room for developing an independent research program. 

We anticipate that this work will involve experiments with both adults and children. Start date is flexible (though fall would be preferred); the position is for one year initially, with the possibility of renewal. For more information about the lab, see our website at langcog.stanford.edu.

If you are interested in applying, please send a cover letter including the names of three references, a CV, and a PDF of a paper that you feel represents your best work to rschneid@stanford.edu. Review of applications will start immediately and continue until the position is filled. 

Sunday, July 5, 2015

Does "time out" hurt your brain?

A recent article in Time Magazine by Daniel Siegel and Tina Payne Bryson argues that "time out" – a disciplinary method that replaces spanking or other physical punishment with enforced social disengagement – is causing harm to children. Siegel and Bryson are authors of The Whole Brain Child, a recent parenting handbook.

Siegel and Bryson make their case using a very weird style of dualistic rhetoric. This is a part and parcel of The Whole Brain Child, whose tagline asks "Do children conspire to make their parents’ lives endlessly challenging? No―it’s just their developing brain calling the shots!" (Personally, I thought it was their spleen.)

Consider this quote from their Time piece:
Studies in neuroplasticity—the brain’s adaptability—have proved that repeated experiences actually change the physical structure of the brain. Since discipline-related interactions between children and caregivers comprise a large amount of childhood experiences, it becomes vital that parents thoughtfully consider how they respond when kids misbehave.
The consequent of this argument – be thoughtful about discipline – seems absolutely true, and practically tautological. It's the first antecedent – the bit about the physical structure of the brain – that worries me. Are we only worried about physical organs? What about the mind, or even the soul? Without some extra premise, for example "...and the physical structure of the brain is more important than what it does," the first part is almost unrelated to the rest of the argument.

Similarly, "In a brain scan, relational pain—that caused by isolation during punishment—can look the same as physical abuse. Is alone in the corner the best place for your child?" The rhetoric is the same: a factual statement about brain science is paired with a statement about parenting, despite their limited relationship to one another. And although relational pain can be incredibly powerful (a couple of years ago, Atul Gawande wrote a wonderful piece on whether solitary confinement should be considered torture), the reason why we believe this has nothing to do with reverse inferences about what the brain shows. It has to do with the behavioral consequences of isolation.

I haven't yet made up my mind about time out. Some parents we know practice it regularly and their children seem fine (though I haven't looked at their brains to make sure they are not physically damaged). And the American Academy of Pediatrics' disciplinary recommendations include a qualified recommendation of time out, with some evidence of efficacy for both older and younger kids. M isn't yet two, and luckily we mostly haven't had too many issues of her acting out – but I can imagine that I wouldn't rule out time out as a punishment.  

More generally, Siegel and Bryson's rhetoric stems from the basic premise that children should be maximally protected from all forms of pain or even discomfort.  Is it better to allow children to have some negative experiences, whether administered by a loving parent or randomly stumbled into? Or should we keep these experiences from them as long as possible, on the thinking that they will have to have them eventually and it is better to establish childhood as a time of greater safety? Though I haven't made up my mind, I think lean towards less protection than Siegel and Bryson do. But it is very frustrating – perhaps even dishonest – to conceal such a critical issue in a fog of brain rhetoric.

Monday, June 29, 2015

A one-trial replication of Chemla & Spector (2011)

tl;dr: Replication of a somewhat controversial finding in experimental semantics/pragmatics.

How do we go beyond the literal semantics of what someone says to infer what they actually meant? Pragmatic inferences – inferences about language use in context – are an important part of language comprehension, and one of the topics I'm most interested in these days. The case study for much of the experimental work on pragmatics has been scalar implicature (in fact, I taught an entire course on this topic last winter). For example, if I say "some of the students passed the test," you can infer that some but not all of the students passed the test. (If I had meant "all passed the test," I probably would have said that).

Although these have been taken as canonical examples of pragmatic inferences, things have gotten a bit more complicated in recent years. A number of linguists have argued that these implicatures are actually generated automatically and are part of the grammar, rather than being generated based on expectations about speakers' intended meanings in context. I won't review the whole literature on this issue (it's quite complicated) but one particularly important phenomenon in the debate is the existence of what are called "local" scalar implicatures – that is, implicatures that are generated within an utterance rather than at the level of the entire utterance.

Here's an example, from a very nice paper by Chemla & Spector (2011). C&S showed participants displays like these:


Then they asked participants to make a graded judgment about the truth of sentences with respect to these pictures. The key sentence (translated into English, the original was in French) is "Exactly one letter is connected with some of its circles." Critically, the different pictures were designed so as to be congruent with different interpretations of the experimental items. C&S posited three such readings:

  • "literal" reading: "exactly one circle is connected with some or all of its circles" (C&S say that the others also must be connected with none, but I'm not sure why);
  • "local" reading: "exactly one circle is connected with some but not all of its circles"
  • "global" reading: "exactly one circle is connected with some but not all of its circles, the others are connected with none"

The local interpretation was the critical one for their purposes, because it required the scalar implicature within the sentence (strengthening "some" to "some but not all") but no implicature at the global level, e.g. that the others are connected with none. As an experimental linking hypothesis, they claimed that participants' degree of truth judgment would be proportional to the number of readings that a particular picture supported. As shown above, the different displays that they used rendered different combinations of readings true.

C&S found data that strongly supported the availability of local readings. In fact, the local reading was even stronger than the literal reading (this wasn't necessarily a prediction, but made their case stronger):


This experimental finding has been controversial, however. Geurts & van Tiel (2014), following previous work by Geurts that didn't find embedded (local) implicatures, have critiqued this and other papers. And a paper I was involved in, Potts et al. (under review), has a much more extensive take on this issue, as well as a different, more naturalistic paradigm.

But in addition to theoretical questions, every time I talk to people about the C&S finding, they bring up doubts about the paradigm that C&S used, whether various replications show order effects, and whether this effect is general across languages (in French, the original language, their "some of its" was certain de, which isn't even a quantifier, technically). In this post, I'm reporting what I say to people when they mention these worries. In particular, I have replicated C&S's basic finding several times in various classes, often in ways that address the critiques above. Here I'll present a version I ran last summer for a course at ESSLLI 2014.

This was a class demo of Amazon Mechanical Turk, so my method was extremely basic. I took exactly the four images above and showed them to four independent groups of 50 US-based participants (total N = 200), who made judgments about whether the target sentence was true of the picture using a seven-point likert scale. So this was a one-trial, completely between-subjects design. Note that there were two manipulation checks relating to descriptions of the display (31 participants failed), and we excluded 39 more for doing more than one trial. Final N was 130.

Here are the data, with 95% CIs:


We replicate the finding that local implicatures were available at detectable levels (e.g., ratings clearly better than those for false sentences). The magnitude is different from C&S, though: the sentences were judged to be far better for the literal pictures than the local ones. Another interesting aspect of this discussion has been about various different response formats. As I mentioned, we used a 7-point likert scale, but participants essentially only used the endpoints (as in the Potts et al. paper above). It seems that participants either "see" a reading or don't. They don't seem to be finding multiple readings and judging the picture to match the sentence to a certain extent, or at least they are not doing this in any substantial number. Here's the histogram:


In sum, we replicate Chemla & Spector, in English, with a standard likert scale, without any fillers, order effects, or extra items to be compared against one another. Some – but not all – participants found an interpretation consistent with local scalar implicature. Code and data available here

Friday, May 1, 2015

An update on automatic belief encoding

Last fall I wrote about our experiences investigating a very influential paper about automatic mind reading by Kovács, Téglás, & Endress (2010; KTE).  In brief, we replicated the intial findings, but we found that they were due to a confound in the experimental design: the timing of the manipulation check was confounded with condition, and appeared to be producing the observed reaction time effect.

One limitation of our work, however, was that we were unable to access the original stimuli and so we relied on our own reconstructions. These reconstructions (there were two) were different in a number of respects that may have decreased our chances of seeing the same effect KTE observed. So we were pleased to learn that Agnes Kovács and her co-authors had posted a subset of her original stimuli (see the bottom of this page). While they didn't post the full video set, we were nevertheless able to modify the videos to create the necessary conditions and rerun our experiment.

As a reminder, the task was detecting a ball behind a box. The consistent pattern we found in our experiments was a crossover interaction between the agent's belief that a ball was present and the participant's belief. This crossover didn't obviously follow from any kind of belief-tracking account, since why would detection of the ball be slow when the agent AND the participant believe it is present. Here are KTE's original data and the theoretically-predicted belief tracking effect:


And here are our original data from a bunch of separate experiments. As you can see, we get the crossover interaction in just about every case, not the belief-tracking pattern that KTE predicted:


And here are the data from the same experiment, run using KTE's stimuli (all methods identical to those used in Experiments 1a and b, above):


So this pattern of RTs looks quite similar and strongly supports the presence of a crossover interaction. These findings provide further support for our account of the original KTE results, and further argue against this paradigm measuring beliefs. 

(Thanks to my coauthors Desmond Ong, Jonathan Philips, and Rebecca Saxe. Desmond did the experiment, and all three reviewed this post).